Footnotes:
1 Memorials (ICAOA and ICAOB), paras. 1.2 (b) and 1.4-1.5; Memorial (ICAOA), paras. 1.21, 1.25-1.27, 1.31-1.32, 2.9 and 2.53-2.55; Memorial (ICAOB), paras. 1.22, 1.261.28, 1.32-1.33, 2.8 and 2.52‑2.54; Memorials, (ICAOA and ICAOB), paras. 3.22 (a), 7.3-7.4 and 7.8; Replies (ICAOA and ICAOB), paras. 2.1-2.4; Reply (ICAOA), paras. 2.35-2.47; and Reply (ICAOB), paras. 2.35-2.45; Replies (ICAOA and ICAOB), para. 4.14; CR 2019/13, of 2 December 2019, pp. 19 and 21-22, paras. 3-4 and 12-14; ibid., pp. 22 and 24, paras. 2 and 11-13; ibid., pp. 26‑28, paras. 8‑10 and 13; ibid., pp. 29‑30, paras. 7-8 and 12-14; ibid., pp. 33 and 38-41, paras. 7 and 23-34; ibid., pp. 58 and 65‑66, paras. 12 and 35-39.
2 Memorial (ICAOA), paras. 2.56-2.67; Memorial (ICAOB), paras. 2.55-2.66; Replies (ICAOA and ICAOB), paras. 1.4, 1.6 and 2.7; CR 2019/13, of 2 December 2019, p. 30, paras. 12-13; ibid., pp. 33‑34 and 37, paras. 7-8 and 18-20; ibid., pp. 70 and 74, paras. 6 and 21; CR 2019/16, of 5 December 2019, pp. 28 and 37-38, paras. 2 and 34. The Riyadh Agreements were seen by the applicant States as an approach to address the alleged threats to regional security, stability and peace. The Riyadh Agreements were seen by States parties as binding; Qatar rejected that it had breached them, held that they were breached by the applicant States, and further rejected that the Riyadh Agreements paved the way for “countermeasures”; CR 2019/15, of 3 December 2019, p. 18, para. 14; CR 2019/15, ibid., pp. 40‑41, para. 20; CR 2019/17, of 6 December 2019, p. 16, para. 9.
3 Memorial (ICAOA), paras. 1.23 and 1.33-1.39; Memorial (ICAOB), paras. 1.24-1.40; Memorials (ICAOA and ICAOB), paras. 5.2 (a), 5.4-5.5, 5.27-5.42, 5.71-5.83, 5.95, 5.119, 5.121-5.122, 5.126, 5.128 (b), 5.130 and 5.133; Replies (ICAOA and ICAOB), paras. 1.7-1.8, 4.7, 4.18, 4.28, 4.33-4.55 and 6.3; CR 2019/13, of 2 December 2019, pp. 34, 36 and 41-42, paras. 8-10, 15-17 and 35-36; ibid., pp. 54 and 61-64, paras. 2 and 21-34; CR 2019/14, of 2 December 2019, pp. 15‑19, paras. 31 and 34-37; CR 2019/16, of 5 December 2019, p. 15, para. 6; ibid., p. 38, paras. 37-38; ibid., p. 56, para. 17.
4 Replies (ICAOA and ICAOB), paras. 4.25-4.27; CR 2019/13, of 2 December 2019, p. 27, para. 10, and p. 36, para. 17.
5 Memorials (ICAOA and ICAOB), para. 5.91; CR 2019/13, of 2 December 2019, p. 67, paras. 46-47; CR 2019/16, of 5 December 2019, pp. 28‑32, paras. 3-13.
6 This case is dealt with in the Judgment concerning the Appeal relating to the Jurisdic‑tion of the ICAO Council under Article 84 of the Convention on International Civil Aviation, which thus mainly concerns the Chicago Convention.
7 There is also a separate point of contention as to the grounds — or otherwise — of the ICAO Council’s decisions.
8 A. A. Cançado Trindade, International Law for Humankind — Towards a New Jus Gentium, 3rd rev. ed., The Hague: Nijhoff/The Hague Academy of International Law, 2020, pp. 454‑455; text originally presented in: A. A. Cançado Trindade, “International Law for Humankind: Towards a New Jus Gentium — General Course on Public International Law — Part I”, 316 Recueil des cours de l’Académie de droit international de la Haye (RCADI) (2005), pp. 31‑439; A. A. Cançado Trindade, “International Law for Humankind: Towards a New Jus Gentium — General Course on Public International Law — Part II”, 317 RCADI (2005), pp. 19‑312.
9 Ph. Allott, “State Responsibility and the Unmaking of International Law”, 29 Harvard International Law Journal (1988), pp. 23‑24.
10 M. Virally, “Panorama du droit international contemporain — Cours général de droit international public”, 183 RCADI (1983), pp. 217‑218.
11 G. Arangio-Ruiz, “Séptimo Informe sobre la Responsabilidad de los Estados”, UN doc. A/CN.4/469, 9 May 1995, pp. 30‑37, 42-43, 46, 49 and 52.
12 Cf., e.g. M. E. O’Connell, “Controlling Countermeasures”, International Responsi‑ bility Today Essays in Memory of O. Schachter (ed. M. Ragazzi), Leiden: Nijhoff, 2005, pp. 49‑62.
13 A. A. Cançado Trindade, “Memorial por um Novo Jus Gentium, o Direito Inter-nacional da Humanidade”, 45 Revista da Faculdade de Direito da Universidade Federal de Minas Gerais, Belo Horizonte/Brazil (2004), pp. 17‑36.
14 A. A. Cançado Trindade, International Law for Humankind — Towards a New Jus Gentium, 3rd rev. ed., op. cit. supra note 8, pp. 454‑456.
15 Yearbook of the International Law Commission (YILC) (1992)-I, p. 88, para. 32; and cf. p. 133, para. 74.
16 Ibid., p. 88, para. 32.
17 Ibid., paras. 31 and 33.
18 Ibid., p. 133, para. 73.
19 Ibid., p. 135, para. 5.
20 Ibid., p. 160, paras. 27 and 29.
21 YILC (1992)-I, p. 160, para. 29.
22 Ibid., p. 161, para. 30.
23 Ibid., pp. 157‑158, para. 15; p. 158, paras. 17-18; and cf. p. 159, para. 22.
24 Ibid., p. 137, paras. 19 and 21; and p. 161, para. 35; and cf. pp. 162‑163, paras. 37 and 45.
25 YILC (1996)-I, pp. 157‑158, paras. 67 and 69-70.
26 Ibid., p. 158, para. 70.
28 YILC (1996)-I, p. 158, para. 76. In the last year of work (2001) of the International Law Commission on the matter, Mr. P. Sreenivasa Rao reiterated his criticisms to the insertion of “countermeasures” in the draft Articles on the matter; cf. YILC (2001)-I, pp. 56‑57, paras. 38 and 42-43.
29 YILC (1994)-I, p. 77, para. 27.
31 Ibid., p. 101, para. 5.
32 Ibid., p. 150, para. 51.
33 YILC (1996)-I, p. 156, para. 56.
35 J. Barboza, “Contramedidas en la Reciente Codificación de la Responsabilidad de los Estados — Fronteras con la Legítima Defensa y el Estado de Necesidad”, 12 Anuario Argentino de Derecho Internacional (2003), p. 39.
38 YILC (2000)-I, p. 279, paras. 26-27.
39 Ibid., p. 280, para. 29.
40 Ibid., p. 283, paras. 1 and 3.
41 Ibid., p. 284, para. 6.
43 YILC (2001)-I, p. 114, para. 75.
44 YILC (1998)-II, Part I, pp. 132 and 151, respectively.
45 Ibid., p. 152, para. 2.
47 YILC (2001)-II, Part I, p. 80.
48 Ibid., p. 81, paras. 1-2.
51 J. Crawford, The International Law Commission’s Articles on State Responsibility — Introduction, Text and Commentaries, Cambridge University Press, 2002, pp. 48‑49.
52 United Nations, Official Records of the General Assembly (UNGAOR), doc. A/C.6/47/SR.28 (1992), p. 15, para. 65.
53 UNGAOR, doc. A/C.6/47/SR.29 (1992), p. 13, para. 58.
56 UNGAOR, doc. A/C.6/55/SR.18 (2000), p. 11, paras. 59-60.
57 Ibid., paras. 60 and 61.
59 UNGAOR, doc. A/C.6/48/SR.27 (1993), p. 14, para. 60.
60 UNGAOR, doc. A/C.6/55/SR.15 (2000), p. 5, para. 29.
62 UNGAOR, doc. A/C.6/47/SR.29 (1992), p. 14, para. 62.
63 Ibid., pp. 14‑15, para. 62.
64 UNGAOR, doc. A/C.6/47/SR.29 (1992), p. 15, para. 70.
65 Ibid., pp. 15-16, paras. 70-71.
66 B. Simma, “Counter-measures and Dispute Settlement: A Plea for a Different Balance”, 5 European Journal of International Law (1994), p. 102.
67 B. Simma, “The Work of the International Law Commission at Its Fifty-Second Session (2000)”, 70 Nordic Journal of International Law (2001), p. 200, and cf. pp. 200‑205 for a narrative review of the ILC draft.
68 O. Schachter, “Dispute Settlement and Countermeasures in the International Law Commission”, 88 American Journal of International Law (1994), p. 472.
69 Ibid., pp. 472 and 477.
70 N. Politis, La justice internationale, Paris : Hachette, 1924, pp. 7‑255, esp. pp. 193‑194 and 249-250. Four decades later, Clarence Wilfred Jenks pondered that the foundation of compulsory jurisdiction lies, ultimately, in the confidence in the rule of law at international level; C. W. Jenks, The Prospects of International Adjudication, London: Stevens, 1964, pp. 101, 117, 757, 762 and 770.
71 A. Truyol y Serra, Noções Fundamentais de Direito Internacional Público, Coimbra:A. Amado Ed., 1952, pp. 90, 98-100 and 104-105.
72 Ibid., pp. 146 and 159.
73 M. Bourquin, “Dans quelle mesure le recours à des négociations diplomatiques est-il nécessaire avant qu’un différend puisse être soumis à la juridiction internationale?”, Hommage d’une génération de juristes au Président Basdevant, Paris : Pedone, 1960, pp. 48‑49.
74 Ibid., p. 51, and cf. p. 52.
76 On the historical evolution of legal personality in the law of nations, cf. H. Mosler, “Réflexions sur la personnalité juridique en droit international public”, Mélanges offerts à H. Rolin — Problèmes de droit des gens, Paris, Pedone, 1964, pp. 228‑251 ; G. Arangio-Ruiz, Diritto Internazionale e Personalità Giuridica, Bologna, Coop. Libr. Univ., 1972, pp. 9‑268; G. Scelle, “Some Reflections on Juridical Personality in International Law”, Law and Politics in the World Community (ed. G. A. Lipsky), Berkeley/Los Angeles, University of California Press, 1953, pp. 49‑58 and 336; J. A. Barberis, “Nouvelles questions concernant la personnalité juridique internationale”, 179 RCADI (1983), pp. 157‑238; A. A. Cançado Trindade, “The Interpretation of the International Law of Human Rights by the Two Regional Human Rights Courts”, Contemporary International Law Issues: Conflicts and Convergence (Proceedings of the III Joint Conference ASIL/T. M. C. Asser Instituut, The Hague, July 1995), The Hague, T. M. C. Asser Instituut, 1996, pp. 157‑162 and 166-167.
77 Cf., for a general study, A. A. Cançado Trindade, Tratado de Direito Internacional dos Direitos Humanos, Porto Alegre: S. A. Fabris Ed., Vol. I, 2nd ed., 2003, pp. 1‑640; Vol. II, 1st ed., 1999, pp. 1‑440; and Vol. III, 2nd ed., 2003, pp. 1‑663; and cf. A. A. Cançado Trindade, “Memorial por um Novo Jus Gentium, o Direito Internacional da Humanidade”, 45 Revista da Faculdade de Direito da Universidade Federal de Minas Gerais (2004), pp. 17‑36.
78 Application instituting proceedings (ICAOA), p. 14, para. 31; Application instituting proceedings (ICAOB), p. 14, para. 31. In sequence, in the ICAOA case, the appellant States have maintained that the ICAO Council lacks jurisdiction ratione materiae under the Chicago Convention, specifically on the lawfulness of the countermeasures. They have argued that the real issue in dispute between the contending Parties concerns “Qatar’s long-standing violations of its obligations under international law”, Memorial (ICAOA), p. 151, para. 5.82), thus exceeding the jurisdiction of the ICAO Council as defined under Article 84 of the Chicago Convention, which is limited to civil aviation, Memorial (ICAOA), pp. 127‑133, paras. 5.27-5.42, and p. 151, para. 5.83.
79 Memorial (ICAOA), p. 215, para. 2.2, Submissions.
80 Cf. D. P. Dryer, “Aristotle’s Conception of Orthos Logos”, 66 The Monist (1983), pp. 106‑119; according to this latter, the recta ratio turns to what is good. The Stoics pursued further the path of ethical virtue, whereby all that is correct is determined, in many aspects, by orthos logos; cf. J. M. Rist, “An Early Dispute about Right Reason”, 66 The Monist (1983), pp. 39‑48.
81 Cicero, On the Commonwealth and on the Laws (ed. J. E. G. Zetzel), Cambridge University Press, 2003 [reed.], Book III, ibid., p. 172. And again in his De Republica (circa end of the years 50 and 46 bc), Cicero opposed the destructive use of force ignoring law and justice; Cicero, The Republic — The Laws, Oxford University Press, 1998, p. 166 (Book III, para. 42).
82 Cf., e.g. G. Lombardi, Ricerche in Tema di ‘Ius Gentium’, Milan: Giuffrè, 1946, pp. 3‑272; G. Lombardi, Sul Concetto di ‘Ius Gentium’, Rome: Istituto di Diritto Romano, 1947, pp. 3‑390; W. Kunkel, Historia del Derecho Romano, 9th ed., Barcelona: Ed. Ariel, 1999, pp. 85‑87; H. C. Clark, “Jus Gentium — Its Origin and History”, 14 Illinois Law Review (1919), pp. 243‑265 and 341-355.
83 P. Guggenheim, “Contribution à l’histoire des sources du droit des gens”, 94 RCADI (1958), pp. 21‑23 and 25.
84 J. Moreau-Reibel, “Le droit de société interhumaine et le ‘jus gentium’ : Essai sur les origines et le développement des notions jusqu’à Grotius”, 77 RCADI (1950), pp. 500‑501, 504 and 506-510.
85 A. Miele, La Comunità Internazionale, Vol. I, 3rd ed., Turin: Giappichelli, 2000, pp. 75, 77-78, 80 and 89.
86 S. Laghmani, Histoire du droit des gens — du jus gentium impérial au jus publicum europaeum, Paris : Pedone, 2003, pp. 90‑94.
87 Even before the “founding fathers” of the law of nations, already in the thirteenth century Thomas Aquinas (1225‑1274), in his Summa Theologiae, expressed the understanding that jus gentium did not need the authority of the legislator, as it could be apprehended by natural reason itself (being thus more perfect than positive law), revealing a conscience of the temporal dimension and being endowed with a universal validity; J.‑P. Rentto, “Jus Gentium: A Lesson from Aquinas”, 3 Finnish Yearbook of International Law (1992), pp. 103, 105, 108-110, 112-113 and 121-122. To Aquinas, law should contribute to the realization of the common good, and thus to the realization of justice, in pursuance of recta ratio; T. Aquinas, Treatise on Law, Washington, DC: Gateway Ed., 2001 [reprint], p. 44; and cf. R. McInerny, Ethica Thomistica — The Moral Philosophy of Thomas Aquinas, rev. ed., Washington DC, Catholic University of America Press, 1997 [reprint], pp. 26, 38 and 46. The jus gentium sought to regulate human relations on an ethical basis, in search of the realization of the common good.
88 Cf. F. de Vitoria, Relecciones — del Estado, de los Indios, y del Derecho de la Guerra, Mexico: Porrúa, 1985, pp. 1‑101; and cf. F. de Vitoria, De Indis — Relectio Prior (15381539), Obras de Francisco de Vitoria — Relecciones Teológicas (ed. T. Urdanoz), Madrid: BAC, 1960, p. 675.
89 F. de Vitoria defined this new jus gentium as quod naturalis ratio inter omnes gentes constituit, vocatur jus gentium. This latter could not derive from the “will” of its subjects of law (including the emerging national States), but was based rather on a lex praeceptiva, apprehended by human reason. Cf. A. A. Cançado Trindade, A Recta Ratio nos Funda‑mentos do Jus Gentium como Direito Internacional da Humanidade, Rio de Janeiro/Belo Horizonte: Academia Brasileira de Letras Jurídicas/Edit. Del Rey, 2005, pp. 21‑61.
90 P. Guggenheim, “Contribution à l’histoire des sources …”, op. cit. supra note 83, pp. 21‑23 and 25.
91 Earlier on, in his De Lege, Francisco de Vitoria, in sustaining the needed search of the common good, added that natural law is found in recta ratio, not in the “will”; F. de Vitoria, La Ley (De Lege — Commentarium in Primam Secundae), Madrid: Tecnos, 1995, pp. 5, 23 and 77. And cf. also G. Fourlanos, Sovereignty and the Ingress of Aliens, Stockholm: Almqvist & Wiksell, 1986, p. 17, and cf. pp. 19‑23, 79-81, 160-161 and 174-175.
92 The universal jus gentium of F. de Vitoria regulated, on the basis of principles of the law of nations (natural law) and of recta ratio, the relations among all peoples, with due respect to their rights, including their freedom of movement (jus communicationis).
93 A. A. Cançado Trindade, “Co-existence and Co-ordination of Mechanisms of International Protection of Human Rights (At Global and Regional Levels)”, 202 RCADI (1987), p. 411; J. Brown Scott, The Spanish Origin of International Law — Francisco de Vitoria and His Law of Nations, Oxford/London: Clarendon Press/H. Milford — Carnegie Endowment for International Peace, 1934, pp. 140, 150, 163-165, 172, 272-273 and 282-283.
94 A. Gómez Robledo, Fundadores del Derecho Internacional, Mexico: UNAM, 1989, pp. 48‑55.
95 Cf. Association Internationale Vitoria-Suarez, Vitoria et Suarez — Contribution des théologiens au droit international moderne, Paris : Pedone, 1939, pp. 169‑170.
96 F. Suárez, Selections from Three Works [De Legibus ac Deo Legislatore, 1612] (orgs. G. L. Williams et alii), Vol. II, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1944, pp. 326‑327 and 341.
97 Ibid., pp. 352 and 357; and cf. B. F. Brown, “The Natural Law as the Moral Basis of International Justice”, 8 Loyola Law Review (1955-1956), p. 60.
98 Cf. A. García y García, “The Spanish School of the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Centuries: A Precursor of the Theory of Human Rights”, 10 Ratio Juris—, University of Bologna (1997), pp. 27 and 29; P. P. Remec, The Position of the Individual in International Law according to Grotius and Vattel, The Hague: Nijhoff, 1960, pp. 216 and 203.
99 P. P. Remec, The Position of the Individual …, op. cit. supra note 98, pp. 217, 219-221 and 243.
100 Cf., in this respect, H. Lauterpacht, “The Grotian Tradition in International Law”, 23 British Yearbook of International Law (1946), pp. 1‑53. The human person and his or her well-being occupy a central position in the system of international relations; H. Lauter-pacht, “The Law of Nations, the Law of Nature and the Rights of Man”, 29 Transactions of the Grotius Society (1943), pp. 7 and 21-31.
101 S. Pufendorf, De Jure Naturae et Gentium Libri Octo (eds. C. H. Oldfather and W. A. Oldfather), Vol. II, Buffalo/N.Y.: W. S. Hein, 1995 [reprint], pp. 202‑203.
102 For references to recta ratio and to conscience in the doctrine of mid-nineteenth century, cf., e.g. J. J. Burlamaqui, The Principles of Natural and Politic Law (reprint of 7th ed.), Columbus: J. H. Riley, 1859, pp. 136, 138-139 and 156‑163.
103 C. W. Jenks, The Common Law of Mankind, London: Stevens, 1958, pp. 66‑69; and cf. also R.‑J. Dupuy, La communauté internationale entre le mythe et l’histoire, Paris : Economica/UNESCO, 1986, pp. 164‑165. It may here be recalled that, in a similar line of thinking to that of the ancient Greeks and of Cicero in ancient Rome, in opposing himself to resort to force, Emmanuel Kant eloquently warned, at the end of the eighteenth century, in his well-known essay on the Perpetual Peace (1795), that human beings cannot be utilized by States for killing, which would not be in accordance with “the law of humankind in our own person”; La paix (Textes choisis, ed. M. Lequan), Paris: Flammarion, 1998, pp. 173‑174.
104 P. P. Remec, The Position of the Individual …, op. cit. supra note 98, pp. 36‑37.
105 Cf., J. Maritain, “The Philosophical Foundations of Natural Law”, Natural Law and World Law — Essays to Commemorate the Sixtieth Birthday of Kotaro Tanaka: Yuhikaku: Japan Academy, 1954, pp. 133‑143.
106 A. A. Cançado Trindade, O Direito Internacional em um Mundo em Transformação, Rio de Janeiro: Edit. Renovar, 2003, p. 547, and cf. pp. 539‑550.
107 As recognized by jusinternationalists themselves: cf., e.g. A. Truyol y Serra, “Théorie du droit international public — Cours général”, 183 RCADI (1981), pp. 142‑143 ; and cf. J. L. Kunz, “Natural Law Thinking in the Modern Science of International Law”, 55 American Journal of International Law (1961), pp. 951‑958, esp. p. 956. And the international community has assumed the vindication of superior common interests; J. A. Carrillo Salcedo, “Derechos Humanos y Derecho Internacional”, 22 Isegoría — Revista de Filosofía Moral y Política, Madrid (2000), p. 75.
108 C. J. Friedrich, Perspectiva Histórica da Filosofia do Direito, Rio de Janeiro: Zahar Ed., 1965, pp. 196‑197, 200-201 and 207. And, for a general study, cf. Y. R. Simon, The Tradition of Natural Law — A Philosopher’s Reflections (ed. V. Kuic), N.Y.: Fordham Univ. Press, 2000 [reed.], pp. 3‑189.
109 Cf. A. Truyol y Serra (ed.), The Principles of Political and International Law in the Work of Francisco de Vitoria, Madrid: Ed. Cultura Hispánica, 1946, pp. 13‑25, 29-32 and 53-73; L. Getino (ed.), Francisco de Vitoria, Sentencias de Doctrina Internacional — Antología, Madrid: Ediciones Fe, 1940, pp. 15‑33 and 129-130; A. Pagden and J. Lawrence (eds.), “Introduction”, Francisco de Vitoria — Political Writings, Cambridge University Press, 1991, pp. XIII – XXIII; R. Hernández, Francisco de Vitoria, Síntesis de Su Vida y Pensamiento, Burgos: Ed. OPE, 1983, pp. 27‑32 and 47-55. And, on the relevance of principles, cf. A. A. Cançado Trindade, “Foundations of International Law: The Role and Importance of Its Basic Principles”, XXX Curso de Derecho Internacional Organizado por el Comité Jurídico Interamericano (2003), Washington, DC: OAS General Secretariat, 2004, pp. 359‑415.
110 Cf. A. A. Cançado Trindade, Tratado de Direito Internacional dos Direitos Humanos, Vol. III, Porto Alegre: S. A. Fabris Ed., 2003, pp. 450‑451; and cf. A. A. Cançado Trindade, “The Procedural Capacity of the Individual as Subject of International Human Rights Law: Recent Developments”, Les droits de l’homme à l’aube du XXIe siècle — K. Vasak Amicorum Liber, Brussels: Bruylant, 1999, pp. 521‑544; A. A. Cançado Trindade, “As Sete Décadas de Projeção da Declaração Universal dos Direitos Humanos (1948-2018) e a Necessária Preservação de Seu Legado”, 73 Revista da Faculdade de Direito da UFMG (2018), pp. 97‑140.
111 Cf., A. A. Cançado Trindade, O Direito Internacional em um Mundo em Transfor‑ mação …, op. cit. supra note 106, pp. 1040‑1109; A. A. Cançado Trindade, “Memorial por um Novo Jus Gentium, o Direito Internacional da Humanidade”, 45 Revista da Faculdade de Direito da Universidade Federal de Minas Gerais (2004), pp. 17‑36; A. A. Cançado Trindade, A Humanização do Direito Internacional, 2nd rev. ed., Belo Horizonte/Brazil: Edit. Del Rey, 2015, pp. 3‑789.
112 A. A. Cançado Trindade, El Acceso Directo del Individuo a los Tribunales Inter‑ nacionales de Derechos Humanos, Bilbao/Spain, Universidad de Deusto, 2001, pp. 9‑104; A. A. Cançado Trindade, “A Personalidade e Capacidade Jurídicas do Indivíduo como Sujeito do Direito Internacional”, Jornadas de Direito Internacional (Mexico City, December 2001), Washington, DC, Subsecretaria de Assuntos Jurídicos da OEA, 2002, pp. 311‑347; A. A. Cançado Trindade, “Vers la consolidation de la capacité juridique internationale des pétitionnaires dans le système interaméricain des droits de la personne”, 14 Revue québécoise de droit international (2001), note 2, pp. 207‑239.
113 Cf. A. A. Cançado Trindade, International Law for Humankind — Towards a New Jus Gentium, 3rd rev. ed., op. cit. supra note 8, pp. 1‑655.
114 F. Crépeau, Droit d’asile — De l’hospitalité aux contrôles migratoires, Brussels: Bruylant, 1995, pp. 17‑353 ; F. Rigaux, “L’immigration : droit international et droits fondamentaux”, Les droits de l’homme au seuil du troisième millénaire — Mélanges en hommage à P. Lambert, Brussels: Bruylant, 2000, pp. 693‑696, and cf. pp. 707‑708, 710‑713, 717-720 and 722 ; and, for a general study, cf. A. A. Cançado Trindade and J. Ruiz de Santiago, La Nueva Dimensión de las Necesidades de Protección del Ser Humano en el Inicio del Siglo XXI, 3rd ed., San José of Costa Rica : UNHCR, 2004, pp. 27‑127.
115 On this latter, cf. A. A. Cançado Trindade, Direito das Organizações Internacionais, 6th ed., Belo Horizonte/Brazil: Edit. Del Rey, 2014, pp. 1‑846.
116 Cf. A. A. Cançado Trindade, “La perspective trans-atlantique : La contribution de l’oeuvre des cours internationales des droits de l’homme au développement du droit public international”, La Convention européenne des droits de l’homme à 50 ans — Bulletin d’information sur les droits de l’homme, note 50 (special number), Strasbourg : Council of Europe, 2000, pp. 8‑9.
117 Cf. G. Abi-Saab, “Les Protocoles Additionnels, 25 ans après”, Les nouvelles frontières du droit international humanitaire (ed. J.‑F. Flauss), Brussels : Bruylant, 2003, pp. 33‑36 ; Y. Sandoz, “L’applicabilité du droit international humanitaire aux actions terroristes”, ibid., pp. 71‑72.
118 J. Pictet, The Principles of International Humanitarian Law, 1st ed., Geneva: ICRC, 1966, p. 36.
119 Positivists and “realists” have not resisted the temptation of disclosing their pride for their method of simple observation of the facts, without being aware that their sense of “pragmatism” without guiding principles disclosed its sinister side (as warned by Bertrand Russell, Sceptical Essays, London: Routledge, 1993 [reprint], p. 49), not seldom leading to abuses and acts of extreme violence.
120 J. Maritain, De la justice politique — Notes sur la présente guerre, Paris : Libr. Plon, 1940, pp. 36‑37, 40-41, 44-45, 88, 90-91, 106-107 and 112-114.
121 H. Lauterpacht, “On Realism, Especially in International Relations”, International Law Being the Collected Papers of Hersch Lauterpacht, Vol. 2, Part I, Cambridge University Press, 1975, pp. 53, 57-62, and 61-65.
122 For a recent study, cf. A. A. Cançado Trindade, “A Consciência sobre a Vontade: Os Tribunais Internacionais e a Humanização do Direito Internacional”, 73 Revista da Faculdade de Direito da UFMG (2018), pp. 827‑860.
123 Cf. A. A. Cançado Trindade, International Law for Humankind — Towards a New Jus Gentium, 3rd rev. ed., op. cit. supra note 8, pp. 1‑655.
124 Cf. A. A. Cançado Trindade, A Humanização do Direito Internacional, 2nd rev. ed., op. cit. supra note 111, pp. 3‑789.
125 A. J. Toynbee, Civilization on Trial, Oxford University Press, 1948, pp. 5, 7-8 and 15.
126 Op. cit. supra note 125, p. 25.
129 Ibid., pp. 162 and 260.
130 S. Weil, Escritos de Londres y Ultimas Cartas [Ecrits de Londres et dernières lettres, 1942-1943], Madrid : Ed. Trotta, 2000, pp. 27‑28, 31, 58 and 180. Given the “suffering unjustly inflicted” upon persons, it is necessary that each person avoids evil and keeps good in her soul, remains away from injustice, and respectfully sustains and transmits justice; ibid., p. 50.
131 S. Weil, Réflexions sur les causes de la liberté et de l’oppression sociale [1934], Paris : Ed. Gallimard, 1955, pp. 41‑43 and 46 (analysis of oppression), English translation entitled Oppression and Liberty, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1958, p. 65; S. Weil, Reflexões sobre as Causas da Liberdade e da Opressão Social [1934], Lisbon: Antígona Ed., 2017, pp. 51‑54 and 57-58 (analysis of oppression).
132 S. Weil, Réflexions sur les causes de la liberté et de l’oppression sociale, op. cit. supra note 131, pp. 45‑46 and page 69 of the English translation ; and cf. S. Weil, Reflexões sobre as Causas da Liberdade e da Opressão Social, op. cit. supra note 131, p. 57.
133 A. A. Cançado Trindade, “Reflexiones sobre la Presencia de la Persona Humana en el Contencioso Interestatal ante la Corte Internacional de Justicia: Desarrollos Recientes”, 17 Anuario de los Cursos de Derechos Humanos de Donostia-San Sebastián, Universidad del País Vasco (2017), pp. 223‑271.
134 A. A. Cançado Trindade, Princípios do Direito Internacional Contemporâneo, 2nd rev. ed., op. cit. infra note 138, p. 451.
135 Andrés Bello, Principios de Derecho Internacional, 3rd ed., Paris: Libr. de Garnier Hermanos, 1873, pp. 11‑12 (the reason, in the light of experience, and keeping in mind the common good).
136 A. A. Cançado Trindade, A Humanização do Direito Internacional, 2nd rev. ed., Belo Horizonte/Brazil: Edit. Del Rey, 2015, Chap. I, pp. 3‑27 (the recta ratio in the foundations of jus gentium as international law for humankind).
137 A. A. Cançado Trindade, “Foundations of International Law: The Role and Importance of Its Basic Principles”, XXX Curso de Derecho Internacional Organizado por el Comité Jurídico Interamericano (2003), Washington, DC: OAS General Secretariat, 2004, p. 367.
138 A. A. Cançado Trindade, Princípios do Direito Internacional Contemporâneo, 2nd rev. ed., Brasília: FUNAG, 2017, p. 452.
139 Such as the fundamental principle of equality and non-discrimination, belonging to the realm of jus cogens (para. 195). In the same dissenting opinion, I further recalled that some of the true prima principia confer to the international legal order its ineluctable axiological dimension, reveal the values which inspire the corpus juris of the international legal order, and, ultimately, provide its foundations themselves. Prima principia conform the substratum of the international legal order, conveying the idea of an objective justice (proper of natural law) (paras. 209 and 211-214).
140 A. A. Cançado Trindade, “Les tribunaux internationaux et leur mission commune de réalisation de la justice : développements, état actuel et perspectives”, 391 Recueil des cours de l’Académie de droit international de La Haye (2017), p. 61.
142 “Civilized” countries can be conceptualized as being those which fully respect and secure, in their respective jurisdictions, the free and full exercise of the rights of individuals and peoples, to the extent and while they so respect and secure them, — this being, ultimately, the best measure of the degree of “civilization attained”; A. A. Cançado Trindade, Tratado de Direito Internacional dos Direitos Humanos, Vol. II, op. cit. supra note 77, p. 344.
143 Already in his pioneering writings, F. de Vitoria conceived the law of nations (droit des gens) as regulating an international community (totus orbis) comprising human beings organized socially in emerging States and conforming humanity; the reparation of violations of their rights reflected an international necessity addressed by the law of nations (droit des gens), with the same principles de justice applying likewise to States and individuals and peoples conforming them. Cf. A. A. Cançado Trindade, “Totus Orbis: A Visão Universalista e Pluralista do Jus Gentium: Sentido e Atualidade da Obra de Francisco de Vitoria”, 24 Revista da Academia Brasileira de Letras Jurídicas, Rio de Janeiro (2008), note 32, pp. 197‑212.
144 For a recent general study, cf. A. A. Cançado Trindade, Os Tribunais Internacio‑ nais e a Realização da Justiça, 3rd rev. ed., Belo Horizonte/Brazil: Edit. Del Rey, 2019, pp. 3‑514, and extensive bibliography contained therein; and cf. also, inter alia, e.g. A. A. Cançado Trindade, “A Consciência sobre a Vontade: Os Tribunais Internacionais e a Humanização do Direito Internacional”, 73 Revista da Faculdade de Direito da UFMG (2018), pp. 827‑860.
145 Cf. A. A. Cançado Trindade, “Les tribunaux internationaux et leur mission commune de réalisation de la justice : développements, état actuel et perspectives”, op. cit. supra note 140, pp. 62 and 68, and cf. pp. 95‑96.
147 Cf. op. cit. supra note 140, pp. 70‑71.
148 Cf. ibid., pp. 94 and 101.
149 Cf. A. A. Cançado Trindade, A Humanização do Direito Internacional, 2nd rev. ed., op. cit. supra note 111, pp. 3‑789 ; A. A. Cançado Trindade, “La Humanización del Derecho Internacional en la Jurisprudencia y la Doctrina : Un Testimonio Personal”, Derecho Internacional Público — Obra Jurídica Enciclopédica (ed. L. Ortiz Ahlf), Mexico : Ed. Porrúa/Escuela Libre de Derecho, 2012, pp. 85‑102.
150 In some decisions over the last decade, the ICJ has known to go beyond the inter-State dimension, in rendering justice, for example: in Ahmadou Sadio Diallo ((Republic of Guinea v. Democratic Republic of the Congo), Merits, Judgment, I.C.J. Reports 2010 (II), p. 639); and on reparations, of 19 June 2012 (Compensation, Judgment, I.C.J. Reports 2012 (I), p. 324); both with my corresponding separate opinions); and case of Frontier Dispute (Burkina Faso v. Niger) (Judgment, I.C.J. Reports 2013, p. 44), Judgment on the merits, of 16 April 2013; also with my corresponding separate opinion); among others.
1 Appeal Relating to the Jurisdiction of the ICAO Council (India v. Pakistan), Judgment, I.C.J. Reports 1972, p. 61, para. 27. The Court wrote that
“[t]he fact that a defence on the merits is cast in a particular form, cannot affect the competence of the tribunal or other organ concerned, —otherwise parties would be in a position themselves to control that competence, which would be inadmissible. As has already been seen in the case of the competence of the Court, so with that of the Council, its competence must depend on the character of the dispute submitted to it and on the issues thus raised — not on those defences on the merits, or other considerations, which would become relevant only after the jurisdictional issues had been settled.”
2 See paragraph 49 of the present Judgment.
3 See paragraph 48 of the present Judgment.
4 United States Diplomatic and Consular Staff in Tehran (United States of America v. Iran), Judgment, I.C.J. Reports 1980, p. 20, para. 37.
6 See e.g. Application of the International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism and of the International Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination (Ukraine v. Russian Federation), Preliminary Objections, Judg‑ ment, I.C.J. Reports 2019 (II), p. 576, para. 28; Certain Iranian Assets (Islamic Republic of Iran v. United States of America), Preliminary Objections, Judgment, I.C.J. Reports 2019 (I), p. 23, para. 36; Obligation to Negotiate Access to the Pacific Ocean (Bolivia v. Chile), Preliminary Objection, Judgment, I.C.J. Reports 2015 (II), p. 604, para. 32.
7 See Article 2 of the Statute of the International Court of Justice.
8 See Article 50 (a) of the Chicago Convention.
9 See paragraph 60 of the present Judgment.
11 See G. F. Fitzgerald, “The Judgment of the International Court of Justice in the Appeal relating to the Jurisdiction of the ICAO Council”, Canadian Yearbook of Interna‑ tional Law, Vol. 12 (1974), pp. 168‑169 (observing that “[i]n the case of the ICAO Council, the persons sitting on the bench are demonstrably the national representatives of the respective member States … Indeed, a perusal of the minutes of the Council meetings of July 28-29, 1971 [in the India v. Pakistan case], shows that some of the members wanted to defer decisions because they wished to await instructions from their governments. Other representatives had apparently received their instructions … The best that can be said is that, in the case of the settlement of disputes in ICAO, the States as such act as judges and their representatives speak on behalf of the States, and not as individuals.”)
12 See paragraphs 60-61 of the present Judgment.
13 See paragraph 61 of the present Judgment.
14 Armed Activities on the Territory of the Congo (New Application: 2002) (Democratic Republic of the Congo v. Rwanda), Jurisdiction and Admissibility, Judgment, I.C.J. Reports 2006, p. 32, para. 65.
15 Ibid., p. 39, para. 88.
1 The term is drawn from the heading to Article 54.
2 Entitled, incidentally, Rules for the Settlement of Differences (emphasis added).
3 See, most recently, Application of the International Convention for the Suppression of the Financing of Terrorism and of the International Convention on the Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination (Ukraine v. Russian Federation), Preliminary Objections, Judgment, I.C.J. Reports 2019 (II), p. 584, para. 57.